The latest issue of Nature has an essay on Hermann Weyl by Frank Wilczek. The essay mainly advertises Weyl’s book Philosophy of Mathematics and Natural Science, originally published in 1926, but updated for the English translation in 1949. I’m embarassed to say I’ve never read this, despite my fascination with Weyl, so I guess I better go out and get ahold of a copy.
About
Quantum Theory, Groups and Representations
Not Even Wrong: The Book
Subscribe to Blog via Email
Join 666 other subscribersRecent Comments
- All Langlands, all the time 6
Peter Woit, Jim+Eadon, kitchin, Peter Woit, Quasiparticular, DH - Is Spacetime Unraveling? 19
Peter Woit, Marty, Peter Woit, Bertie, Mathias, Mark Hillery [...] - Richard S. Hamilton 1943-2024 6
David Ross, James Allen Isenberg, Matt Grayson, Jason Starr, Jason Starr, Ian Stopher - This Week's Hype 48
Peter Woit, Karl Young, Peter Woit, Martin G, Thomas Corrigan, Peter Woit [...] - Podcast About String Theory, Other Items 23
Hansi, Anon X, Aaron Cofer, Scott Caveny, lll, Peter Woit [...]
- All Langlands, all the time 6
Categories
- abc Conjecture (21)
- Book Reviews (122)
- BRST (13)
- Euclidean Twistor Unification (15)
- Experimental HEP News (153)
- Fake Physics (8)
- Favorite Old Posts (50)
- Film Reviews (15)
- Langlands (52)
- Multiverse Mania (163)
- Not Even Wrong: The Book (27)
- Obituaries (35)
- Quantum Mechanics (23)
- Quantum Theory: The Book (7)
- Strings 2XXX (27)
- Swampland (20)
- This Week's Hype (141)
- Uncategorized (1,288)
- Wormhole Publicity Stunts (15)
Archives
Links
Mathematics Weblogs
- Alex Youcis
- Alexandre Borovik
- Anton Hilado
- Cathy O'Neil
- Daniel Litt
- David Hansen
- David Mumford
- David Roberts
- Emmanuel Kowalski
- Harald Helfgott
- Jesse Johnson
- Johan deJong
- Lieven Le Bruyn
- Mathematics Without Apologies
- Noncommutative Geometry
- Persiflage
- Pieter Belmans
- Qiaochu Yuan
- Quomodocumque
- Secret Blogging Seminar
- Silicon Reckoner
- Terence Tao
- The n-Category Cafe
- Timothy Gowers
- Xena Project
Physics Weblogs
- Alexey Petrov
- AMVA4NewPhysics
- Angry Physicist
- Capitalist Imperialist Pig
- Chad Orzel
- Clifford Johnson
- Cormac O’Raifeartaigh
- Doug Natelson
- EPMG Blog
- Geoffrey Dixon
- Georg von Hippel
- Jacques Distler
- Jess Riedel
- Jim Baggott
- John Horgan
- Lubos Motl
- Mark Goodsell
- Mark Hanman
- Mateus Araujo
- Matt Strassler
- Matt von Hippel
- Matthew Buckley
- Peter Orland
- Physics World
- Resonaances
- Robert Helling
- Ross McKenzie
- Sabine Hossenfelder
- Scott Aaronson
- Sean Carroll
- Shaun Hotchkiss
- Stacy McGaugh
- Tommaso Dorigo
Some Web Pages
- Alain Connes
- Arthur Jaffe
- Barry Mazur
- Brian Conrad
- Brian Hall
- Cumrun Vafa
- Dan Freed
- Daniel Bump
- David Ben-Zvi
- David Nadler
- David Vogan
- Dennis Gaitsgory
- Eckhard Meinrenken
- Edward Frenkel
- Frank Wilczek
- Gerard ’t Hooft
- Greg Moore
- Hirosi Ooguri
- Ivan Fesenko
- Jacob Lurie
- John Baez
- José Figueroa-O'Farrill
- Klaas Landsman
- Laurent Fargues
- Laurent Lafforgue
- Nolan Wallach
- Peter Teichner
- Robert Langlands
- Vincent Lafforgue
Twitter
Videos
“The question for the ultimate foundations and the ultimate meaning of mathematics remains open; we do not know in which direction it will find its final solution nor even whether a final objective answer can be expected at all. “Mathematizing” may well be a creative activity of man, like language or music, of primary originality, whose historical decisions defy complete objective rationalization.” — Hermann Weyl (Gesammelte Abhandlungen)
http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Hermann_Weyl
I would sure like to see that article.
-drl
In honor of Weyl:
What is the analog in distant parallelism, of Weyl’s ansatz in distant measure (Riemannian geometry)? Has anybody investigated? A first guess is
L(A) g_mn = Am An
where L(A) is the Lie derivative. It looks to me like “distant parallelism” gets changed to “distant parallelism with respect to an arbitrary quadric” (just a guess, haven’t investigated yet). It would be very interesting if the covariant derivative in this looked like dm + i Am.
-drl
Peter, I’ve seen a couple references to Nature on the site – how much of the journal do you manage to read? As a theorist in biophysics I actually feel like I have to get through most of Nature and Nature Genetics in addition to the physics journals (mostly PRL and PRE and, most of all, arxiv; of course I still indulge my particle hobby and glance at PRD and hep-th)..but I always wondered how many people (especially in the particle community) read Nature.
I confess that my reading of Nature has always been kind of like just reading the cartoons in the New Yorker, i.e. I ignore the research articles (except on very rare occasions), and just skim the news items and things like book reviews and essays. Few technical articles in the fields I really know about (math and particle physics) ever appear in Nature, and when they do, they’ve often been placed there by people who are more interested in getting their names in the popular press than in communicating with their fellow physicists or mathematicians (who generally don’t read Nature). Maybe “Nature Physics” will be different.
Until a few months ago I used to skim copies of Nature when I saw them appear down in the library. More recently I tend to look at the online version.
Pingback: It's equal but it's different
Nature 437, 1095 (20 October 2005) | doi: 10.1038/4371095a
An explorer and surveyor
Frank Wilczek1
1. Frank Wilczek is at the Center for Theoretical Physics, Massachusetts Institute of Technology, Cambridge, Massachusetts, 02142, USA.
Top of page
Abstract
Hermann Weyl made prescient contributions to both mathematics and physics, but also strove to understand reality as a whole.
Hermann Weyl was, according to Fields medallist Michael Atiyah, “one of the greatest mathematicians of the first half of the twentieth century”. Every great mathematician is great in their own way, but Weyl’s way was particularly special. Unlike most modern scientists who choose one or a few specific areas to explore and look neither sideways nor back, Weyl surveyed the whole world. He sought truth and beauty with a discriminating and far-seeing eye.
Weyl’s most unique work is Philosophy of Mathematics and Natural Science. No one else could have written it, and no other book I know is like it. I have consulted it many times, and each time I’ve come away enriched. My main purpose here is to direct readers to that book. But since space remains, let me add some background information.
Weyl, who died in 1955 at the age of 70, was a student of David Hilbert at the Georg-August University in Göttingen, Germany, and thus stood in the line of intellectual descent from Carl Gauss, Bernhard Riemann and Lejeune Dirichlet. Upon Hilbert’s retirement, Weyl was invited to take up his chair, but conditions in 1930s Germany and an attractive offer from the new Institute for Advanced Study conspired to bring him to Princeton, where he stayed. With Albert Einstein and John von Neumann, Weyl made the trinity of refugee stars that gave the institute its inimitable scientific lustre.
Einstein and von Neumann had both grown up in the grand German literary and pan-European cultural tradition that was rocked and then shattered by the two world wars. But more than the rebellious Einstein or the protean von Neumann, Weyl embodied that tradition, and his Philosophy of Mathematics and Natural Science reflects it in focus, style and erudition.
The main body of text was written in German in 1926, as an article for R. Oldenburg’s Handbuch der Philosophie. In 1949, for the English translation, Weyl altered many details and added seven appendices, comprising almost a hundred pages. These centre on relevant scientific events in the intervening years — his passages on Gödel’s theorem, and on quantum mechanics and causality are especially brilliant. But the core of the book had its genesis in the vanished handbook tradition of magisterial reviews in natural philosophy.
Unfortunately we are unable to provide accessible alternative text for this. If you require assistance to access this image, or to obtain a text description, please contact npg@nature.com
ARCHIVES OF THE INST. OF ADVANCED STUDY
Hermann Weyl touched on questions that are relevant today.
In the introduction, Weyl declares the roots of his literary style: “I was bound by the German literary and philosophical tradition in which I grew up.” As an example of that style, let me quote a passage that I think ranks among the most beautiful and profound passages in all literature: “The objective world simply is, it does not happen. Only to the gaze of my consciousness, crawling along the lifeline of my body, does a section of this world come to life as a fleeting image in space which continuously changes in time.”
Weyl’s work is also remarkable for its erudition. René Descartes, Gottfried Leibniz, David Hume and Immanuel Kant enter into the discussion as familiar friends. From time to time important literary or philosophical passages are quoted in the original French, German, or even Greek. Weyl’s erudition is not vain display — he is far above that — but a touching assumption of shared culture. Of course the reader will feel at home in this milieu, he seems to assume.
In his biographical memoir of Weyl, Atiyah also talked about Weyl’s work in mathematics, saying: “The last 50 years have seen a remarkable blossoming of just those areas that Weyl initiated. In retrospect, one might almost say that Weyl defined the agenda and provided the proper framework for what followed.” Weyl’s contributions in physics were more sporadic, but they were significant, and likewise remarkably prescient. In particular, Weyl proposed, and named, the concept of ‘gauge invariance’, which came to dominate fundamental physics during the second half of the twentieth century.
Evidently, Weyl’s intuitions have an excellent track record. By now, parts of the Philosophy of Mathematics and Natural Science are dated, of course. Those parts retain interest as intellectual history, because Weyl’s understandings, being close to the best that was possible in their time, serve as benchmarks. But beyond that, Philosophy of Mathematics and Natural Science touches great questions that remain very much alive. Near the end of the book, after a penetrating critique of the concept of causality, Weyl turns to what he calls the body–soul problem — what we know today as the problem of consciousness.
“It is an altogether too mechanical conception of causality that views the mutual effects of body and soul as being so paradoxical that one would rather resort, like Descartes, to the occasionalistic intervention of God or, like Leibniz, to a harmony instituted at the beginning of time.
The real riddle, if I am not mistaken, lies in the double position of the ego: it is not merely an existing individual which carries out real psychic acts, but also ‘vision’, a self-penetrating light (sense-giving consciousness, knowledge, image, or however you may call it); as an individual capable of positing reality, its vision open to reason; ‘a force into which an eye has been put’, as Fichte says.”
The fullest enlightenment comes only to those who, like Weyl, discern its absence, seek it, and recognize it when it arrives.
FURTHER READING
Atiyah, M. in Biographical Memoirs Vol. 82 , 1–13 (Natl Acad., Washington DC, 2002).
Weyl, H. Philosophy of Mathematics and Natural Science (Princeton Univ. Press, Princeton, 1949).